Scientific MOOCs follower. Author of Airpocalypse, a techno-medical thriller (Out Summer 2017)


Welcome to the digital era of biology (and to this modest blog I started in early 2005).

To cure many diseases, like cancer or cystic fibrosis, we will need to target genes (mutations, for ex.), not organs! I am convinced that the future of replacement medicine (organ transplant) is genomics (the science of the human genome). In 10 years we will be replacing (modifying) genes; not organs!


Anticipating the $100 genome era and the P4™ medicine revolution. P4 Medicine (Predictive, Personalized, Preventive, & Participatory): Catalyzing a Revolution from Reactive to Proactive Medicine.


I am an early adopter of scientific MOOCs. I've earned myself four MIT digital diplomas: 7.00x, 7.28x1, 7.28.x2 and 7QBWx. Instructor of 7.00x: Eric Lander PhD.

Upcoming books: Airpocalypse, a medical thriller (action taking place in Beijing) 2017; Jesus CRISPR Superstar, a sci-fi -- French title: La Passion du CRISPR (2018).

I love Genomics. Would you rather donate your data, or... your vital organs? Imagine all the people sharing their data...

Audio files on this blog are Windows files ; if you have a Mac, you might want to use VLC (http://www.videolan.org) to read them.

Concernant les fichiers son ou audio (audio files) sur ce blog : ce sont des fichiers Windows ; pour les lire sur Mac, il faut les ouvrir avec VLC (http://www.videolan.org).


Les prélèvements "à coeur arrêté" en France ont repris depuis 2006

==> Lire cet article sur Wikipedia : cliquer ici.

L’arrêt cardiaque ne signifie plus simplement la mort de l’individu. La loi du 21 avril 2005 établit la procédure des prélèvements d’organes "à cœur arrêté" - procédure qui permet qu’une situation d’arrêt cardiaque devienne une source de greffons. Un patient dont les fonctions cardiaques et respiratoires sont en arrêt persistant peut désormais devenir donneur d’organes. Dans cette situation, le foie, les reins et les poumons peuvent être prélevés : les reins constituent l’essentiel des greffons prélevés, néanmoins des équipes pilotes étudient actuellement la possibilité de prélever les poumons sur donneurs "à cœur arrêté". Afin d’éviter toute confusion, rappelons que les donneurs "décédés" peuvent être en état de "mort encéphalique" (dans ce cas le coeur peut être prélevé), ou en état d’"arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant" (dans ce cas, le coeur ne peut pas être prélevé, car il serait en trop mauvais état pour être greffé avec succès). Le cœur peut être prélevé sur des patients en état de mort encéphalique uniquement.
1. La technique de prélèvement d’organes dite "à coeur arrêté" :

Après avoir été abandonnés vers la fin des années 60, puisqu’entre 1968 et 2006, seuls les prélèvements d’organes sur donneurs en état de mort encéphalique ont été pratiqués en France (pour ce qui est des donneurs "décédés"), les prélèvements "à coeur arrêté" ont repris en 2006. Cette technique de prélèvement d’organes, sur patients "en état d’arrêt cardiaque et circulatoire persistant", est très utilisée dans certains pays, où elle peut concerner jusqu’à 50 pour cent des donneurs.

Le saviez-vous ? Parmi les premiers prélèvements d’organes effectués en France, beaucoup l’ont été sur patients "à cœur arrêté". Il ne s’agit donc pas là d’une nouvelle technique. Une anecdote quelque peu macabre : les premiers prélèvements de reins effectués en France dans cette situation l’ont été sur des condamnés à mort, guillotinés à la prison de La Santé. Juste après leur exécution, une équipe médicale se précipitait sur eux, afin de remplacer leur sang par des liquides de refroidissement, et une ambulance conduisait à l’hôpital ces "candidats" au prélèvement d’organes (reins)...

Source : Deuxièmes Journées Internationales d’Ethique : "Donner, recevoir un organe, droit, dû, devoir", au Palais Universitaire de Strasbourg, du 29 au 31 mars 2007 : Professeur Philippe Wolf : "La transplantation : quelle histoire !?"
Lien : http://www.canalc2.tv/video.asp?idvideo=6012

2. Prélèvements "à coeur arrêté" et classification de Maastricht :

Récemment, à l’échelle internationale, cinq types de situations pouvant conduire à un prélèvement à cœur arrêté ont été identifiés dans une classification dite "de Maastricht", qui décrit les donneurs potentiels :

Classe I : Les personnes qui arrivent à l’hôpital en arrêt cardiaque et pour lesquelles le prélèvement d’organes est envisagé si la durée de l’arrêt cardiaque est inférieure à 30 minutes. Il s’agit d’un arrêt cardiaque constaté en dehors de tout secours médical ou para médical et s’avérant immédiatement ou secondairement irréversible.

Classe II : Les personnes qui ont un arrêt cardiaque en présence des secours, et dont la réanimation (massage cardiaque et respiration artificielle) échoue. C’est l’arrêt cardiaque dit "réfractaire".

Classe III : Arrêt cardiaque irréversible survenu après arrêt des soins programmé. Les personnes pour lesquelles on décide d’un arrêt de la réanimation. Il y a non pas échec de la réanimation, mais arrêt des soins. Cette situation représente dans certains pays étrangers la source de prélèvement la plus importante (aux USA notamment) et la plus facile à organiser. Elle n’est pas envisagée en France pour l’instant, afin d’éviter toute confusion entre une décision d’arrêt de soins et l’intention d’un prélèvement d’organes.

Classe IV : Un arrêt cardiaque irréversible survenant au cours d’un état de mort encéphalique primitive, pendant sa prise en charge en réanimation : les personnes en état de mort encéphalique qui font un arrêt cardiaque irréversible alors qu’elles se trouvent en réanimation.

Classe V : elle est l’équivalent de la Classe II, sauf qu’au lieu de se trouver hors de l’hôpital, le patient y est déjà.

3. Disparité des pratiques à l’échelle internationale :

La pratique en France : les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" se font essentiellement sur des donneurs appartenant à la catégorie ou classe I ou II (situation d’échec de la réanimation). Les donneurs potentiels appartenant à la catégorie III (situation d’arrêt de soins) sont exclus pour le moment.

La pratique à l’étranger : L’exemple des USA : les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" se font essentiellement sur des donneurs appartenant à la catégorie ou classe III (situation d’arrêt de soins).

En règle générale, un pays donné recrute ses donneurs soit dans les classes I et II de Maastricht, soit dans la classe III, l’un des deux choix tendant à exclure l’autre. Un pays qui prélève des patients de la classe III aura tendance à recruter très peu de donneurs dans les autres classes (I ou II essentiellement). Inversement, un pays qui prélève des patients de la classe I ou II ne recrutera pas de donneurs de la classe III (exemple de la France). Ces deux choix, qui ont tendance à s’exclure mutuellement, correspondent à deux situations bien distinctes : les classes I et II correspondent à des situations d’échec de la réanimation, tandis que la classe III correspond à une situation d’arrêt de soins.

4. Les contraintes des prélèvements "à coeur arrêté" : une course contre le temps :

Première étape :
Entre l’arrêt cardio-pulmonaire et le début de la réanimation cardio-pulmonaire, il ne faut pas que plus de 30 mn s’écoulent. La réanimation cardio-pulmonaire constitue la première étape. Elle doit être au moins de 30 mn. Cette réanimation a pour but de sauver la vie du patient. La situation présentée ici correspond à celle de l’arrêt cardiaque "réfractaire", où la réanimation va être considérée comme "futile" (terme anglais signifiant: inutile, vaine). Il faut moins de 120 mn entre le début de l’arrêt cardio-circulatoire et l’institution d’une technique de perfusion des organes, pour laquelle il y a deux techniques, toutes deux invasives :
  • soit celle du refroidissement "in situ" (l’idée est de permettre le refroidissement des organes pour assurer leur conservation : on perfuse un liquide froid au niveau des reins au moyen d’une sonde à doubles ballonnets : la "sonde de Gillot"),
  • soit celle de la "circulation extracorporelle" (CEC), qui se fait à thorax ouvert : une thoracotomie est pratiquée afin d’assurer la déviation de la circulation du sang : une machine relaie les fonctions du cœur et des poumons, pour assurer la perfusion des organes. Cette même machine sert aux opérations à cœur ouvert, en chirurgie cardiaque dite "traditionnelle" ou "invasive".

Deuxième étape :
Pendant cinq minutes, les tentatives de réanimation cardio-pulmonaire infructueuses, d'une durée de 30 mn, sont arrêtées. Ce court laps de temps, ces cinq minutes, permettent de constater le décès. C’est ainsi que ces cinq minutes constituent la frontière entre deux étapes : entre celle où on poursuivait une tentative de réanimation en vue de sauver le patient (tentative de réanimation d'une durée de 30 mn), et celle où une réanimation va être entreprise, mais avec un tout autre objectif, puisque cette nouvelle tentative vise à assurer la conservation des organes de ce patient "candidat" au prélèvement d’organes, considéré comme mort au bout de ce court laps de temps d’une durée de cinq minutes. La première réanimation est clairement dans l’intérêt du patient ; la deuxième réanimation, celle pour les organes chez un patient déclaré mort, constituerait un "acharnement thérapeutique déraisonnable" et par ailleurs interdit par la loi Léonetti d’avril 2005, dite "loi sur la fin de vie", si le but poursuivi était toujours de sauver ce patient. On peut donc dire que la deuxième réanimation va clairement à l’encontre de l’intérêt du patient sur qui elle est pratiquée, mais sert les intérêts des patients en attente de greffe, puisque c’est une réanimation en vue de la conservation des organes jusqu’à leur prélèvement. Le patient sur qui est pratiquée cette réanimation a perdu ses droits de malade en fin de vie. Ce mort réanimé est devenu un simple pourvoyeur d’organes.

Troisième étape :
C’est la réanimation invasive qui suit le constat de décès (rédigé dans le court laps de temps des cinq minutes qui constituent la deuxième étape). Cette réanimation est pratiquée dans le but d’obtenir des greffons viables. Le patient est devenu un simple réservoir d’organes.

5. Controverses :

Les cinq minutes, qui font office de frontière entre deux réanimations poursuivant des buts opposés, revêtent une importance cruciale sur le plan de l’éthique et de la législation.

a.) Sur le plan de l’éthique :

On comprend que la déontologie médicale qui préside au prélèvement d’organes sur donneurs "décédés" est particulière. Elle est d’ailleurs controversée dans le milieu médical lui-même, puisque tout médecin est censé poursuivre le bien du seul patient qu’il a en charge, et non pas sacrifier l’intérêt dudit patient à celui de la communauté (des patients en attente de greffe). Le médecin ou chirurgien acteur des transplantations se trouve donc pris dans un dilemme, opposant service à l’individu et service à la collectivivité.

b.) Sur le plan de la législation :

Pour que les prélèvements d’organes puissent recueillir l’acceptation sociétale, il faut que le donneur soit mort (dans le cas des prélèvements d’organes sur donneurs "décédés"). Or pour que les greffes soient efficaces, il faut que le donneur soit aussi mort que nécessaire aux yeux de la loi, tout en étant aussi vivant que possible sur le plan médical : les greffons prélevés sur un mort ne peuvent aider personne. Ce dilemme revêt une importance sur le plan de l’éthique et de la loi.

En dernière analyse, une définition légale de la mort, dans le but de permettre l’activité des prélèvements d’organes sur donneurs "décédés", se heurte à des contradictions insurmontables. Il y aurait un conflit insurmontable entre la nécessité de laisser passer suffisamment de temps pour que le décès d’un donneur d’organes potentiel puisse être raisonnablement prononcé, et la nécessité de prélever des organes (greffons) viables, ces organes ou greffons devant être prélevés le plus tôt possible. Face à ce constat, certains pays recommandent d’arrêter les tentatives, vouées à l’échec, de fournir une définition légale des critères de la mort, dans le but de permettre des prélèvements d’organes. Ce n’est pas l’orientation choisie par la France, qui maintient les tentatives de définition des critères de la mort d’un point de vue légal, dans le but de recueillir l’acceptation sociétale vis à vis des prélèvements d’organes sur donneur "mort". Ces définitions légales font néanmoins l’objet d’un consensus mou, c’est-à-dire qu’elles ne font pas l’unanimité au sein du corps médical français et international. Face à ces disparités des pratiques et des avis scientifiques, certains médecins demandent à ce que la distinction soit faite entre les états qui permettent les prélèvements d’organes et l’état de mort, étant bien entendu que la "mort encéphalique" et "l’arrêt cardiaque et circulatoire persistant" sont des états qui permettent les prélèvement d’organes, mais que ces états sont distincts de l’état de mort.

c.) Le diagnostic de la mort chez les patients en état d’"arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant" :

Au bout d’un certain nombre de minutes (30 environ), on considère que la réanimation est devenue vaine (« futile » en anglais, c’est-à-dire inutile), qu’il n’y a plus de chance de survie pour le malade. On arrête, on est donc dans un processus d’arrêt de la réanimation cardio-pulmonaire, et on va attendre 5 mn sans RCP (Réanimation Cardio Pulmonaire), afin de vérifier que sans réanimation il n’y a pas de retour à une respiration spontanée. L’ECG (Electrocardiogramme) doit être plat ou agonique. Ce tracé agonique peut durer plusieurs heures. C’est au cours de ces cinq minutes que le certificat de décès va être signé, puis la RCP est reprise, mais chez un patient qui a été déclaré décédé. Pourquoi cette période de 5 mn ? Lorsqu’il y a eu une période d’arrêt cardiaque sans RCP, puis une RCP jugée inutile au bout de 30 mn, si de nouveau la RCP est arrêtée pendant 5 mn, les neurones n’auront pas pu survivre. Le diagnostic de mort sur le plan neuronal est certain. Ce diagnostic n’atteste cependant pas la destruction du cerveau, qui n’est pas requise pour les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" : dans cette situation, on ne peut savoir avec certitude à quel moment un tel patient se trouve en état de mort encéphalique. Or rappelons qu’en France, la définition légale de la mort repose sur la mort du cerveau, et non sur la mort sur le plan neuronal. Déclarer qu’un patient dont les fonctions cardiaques et respiratoires sont en arrêt persistant est décédé est donc paradoxal : le rapport de l’Académie Nationale de Médecine du 14/03/2007, intitulé "Prélèvements d’organes à cœur arrêté", stipule :

"Depuis 1968 et jusqu’à présent, le prélèvement a été limité aux donneurs à cœur
battant en état de mort cérébrale. Dans le sillage des expériences étrangères,
la loi française a ouvert depuis août 2005 une voie nouvelle, celle des ’décédés
présentant un arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant’ autorisant le
prélèvement des reins et du foie."

Ce même rapport précise :

"Il n’y a qu’une seule forme de mort : la mort encéphalique, qu’elle soit
primitive ou secondaire à l’arrêt cardiaque".

Si on suit cette logique, d’un point de vue légal, le patient en arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant devrait être déclaré mort lors du prélèvement de ses organes, et non avant, alors que la mort du cerveau n’est pas requise, ni vérifiée. La mort neuronale n’équivaut pas à la mort cérébrale. Le diagnostic de mort dans le cas d’un patient candidat aux prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" fait donc l’objet de dissensions au sein de la communauté médicale et scientifique, tant en France qu’à l’échelle internationale. Il semblerait que les différentes tentatives visant à justifier les prélèvements d’organes sur donneurs "décédés" à l’aide d’une définition des critères de la mort d’un point de vue juridique n’aient pas abouti, dans le cas de la "mort encéphalique" comme dans le cas des patients "décédés présentant un arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant". En effet, il existe une controverse au sujet de la loi en France, qui fait équivaloir la mort avec une incompétence du cerveau (loi de bioéthique de 1996, revue en 2004). En ce qui concerne les prélèvements "à coeur arrêté", nous avons vu que le constat de décès est basé sur l’arrêt des fonctions du coeur et des poumons, sans que soit vérifiée la destruction du cerveau (mort encéphalique).

Rappelons deux principes fondamentaux :

  • La mort, dans son acception traditionnelle, se définit par la cessation irréversible des fonctions du coeur, des poumons et du cerveau.
  • Ces trois conditions ne sont jamais remplies lors d'un constat de décès permettant le prélèvement des organes d'un donneur "décédé".

Sources :
1. http://www.sfmu.org/documents/consensus/po_rapport_2007.pdf
2. http://www.sfar2008.com/podcast.html
3. "PRELEVEMENTS A COEUR ARRETE - Enjeux éthiques". Dr. Marc Guerrier, Espace Ethique de l’AP-HP, 15 novembre 2006.
Lien : http://www.espace-ethique.org/fr/transplantations.php

Transplantation d'organes et médiation éthique

Un acteur des transplantations affirmait récemment, lors d’un congrès rassemblant des spécialistes de la réanimation :

"les prélèvements ‘à cœur arrêté’ rencontrent une large adhésion de la part de la société".
Cette affirmation pourrait paraître paradoxale, puisqu’à l’heure actuelle, aucun discours public sur les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" n’a été mis en place. Comment le consentement éclairé au don de ses organes à sa mort, inscrit dans la loi, va-t-il pouvoir être recueilli auprès d’un grand public qui, tout en ignorant tout ou presque des prélèvements "à cœur arrêté", est sans cesse sollicité afin de prendre position pour ou contre le don de ses organes à sa mort ?


Quels sont les enjeux d'une médiation éthique dans le contexte des transplantations d'organes ?
Dans le contexte actuel, qui est celui d’une volonté de promouvoir au maximum les transplantations d’organes, l’information ne s’affranchit jamais de la promotion du don d’organes, au motif de l’impératif "éthique" d’encourager les bonnes volontés face à la pénurie de greffons. Chaque hôpital, chaque clinique a pour mission de promouvoir les transplantations d’organes : identifier des donneurs "morts", fournir des greffons viables, greffer les patients en attente d’un organe. Le discours public se fait l’écho de cet impératif de promotion des transplantations. Cette fuite en avant vise à cacher le talon d’Achille des transplantations : la pénurie de greffons. A y regarder de plus près, on s’aperçoit que la promotion du don d’organes, les prélèvements et greffes à tout prix et pour tout prix font des victimes dans chaque "camp" (donneurs ou donneurs potentiels ; receveurs ou receveurs potentiels). Les patients en attente de greffe et leur famille s’attendent à recevoir l’organe salvateur. Ils refusent de commencer un processus de deuil, tous les espoirs sont placés dans l’Attente de l’Organe et du Don. Pour peu que le proche en attente d’organe vienne à décéder faute de greffe, le ressentiment sera immense (à la mesure de l’espoir suscité) et le deuil pathologique. Ainsi les parents de la petite Mathilde, 4 ans, ont écrit à Monsieur Nicolas Sarkozy le jeudi 11/10/2007. Mathilde attend un cœur depuis juin 2007. Je cite un extrait de cette lettre :


"Nous sentons bien le souffle aigre de la fatalité et l’échéance qui
approche. (...) Nous n’acceptons pas cette renonciation annoncée, car des
solutions existent. Et nous voulons poser cette question simple : qu’attendent
les pouvoirs publics pour mettre enfin en œuvre les mesures qui s’imposent ? Et
dont on sait qu’elles sont efficaces ? En Espagne, pas très loin de chez nous...
Nous voulons des actes, pas des paroles. (...) C’est pourquoi, nous demandons
instamment à Monsieur Nicolas Sarkozy de déclarer le don d’organes et la greffe
Grande Cause Nationale. (...)Il faut que la société Française toute entière se
mobilise pour mettre fin à ce scandale insupportable de la mort de nos enfants,
parce que les pouvoir publics ne font pas ce qu’il faut pour leur donner accès
au traitement qui les sauverait. C’est pourquoi nous invitons tous nos
compatriotes à signer l’Appel à la solidarité nationale de Mathilde. Nous
remettrons personnellement cette pétition à Monsieur le Président de la
République."
Source : http://lappeldemathilde.blogspot.com/

Pour la famille de cette jeune patiente en attente de greffe, la pénurie de greffons est imputable à ... une erreur de choix politique. Il s’agit là d’un malentendu aux conséquences gravissimes, que le Professeur Bernard Debré analyse dans son livre intitulé "Nous t’avons tant aimé. L’euthanasie, l’impossible loi", publié en 2004 aux éditions du Cherche-Midi (Document). Il identifie ainsi "les conséquences gravissimes d’un malentendu qui n’en finit pas de se développer, à l’égard du clonage". Greffer, c’est bien ; cloner, c’est mal.

"Or seul le clonage thérapeutique peut parvenir à régler la question des
greffes d’organes".
Demander à ce que les greffes soient déclarées grande cause nationale, c’est oublier un peu vite que les greffes représentent un problème complexe et douloureux :

"les greffes d’organes, matière à la fois compliquée, à cause des
rejets, et douloureuse, en raison du manque chronique... d’organes à greffer !"
(Ouvrage cité, p. 107).
Faut-il déclarer le clonage thérapeutique grande cause nationale, et non le don d’organes ? Rappelons que la définition légale de la mort repose, depuis 1968, sur une incompétence du cerveau, et ce, pour deux raisons : permettre deux pratiques de fin de vie : les prélèvements d’organes et l’arrêt des soins :

"La nouvelle définition de la mort cérébrale est née en 1968 à la suite du
progrès des techniques de réanimation (ventilation artificielle et réanimation
cardio-pulmonaire) et du développement des pratiques de transplantation. ’Ce
changement de législation a permis de résoudre le double problème que posait,
d’une part la surcharge des lits occupés par des patients qui ne retrouveraient
plus la conscience et, d’autre part, la demande croissante d’organes pour la
transplantation. La définition de mort cérébrale permet d’annuler les obstacles
auparavant légaux de deux pratiques désormais très courantes en fin de vie : les
prélèvements d’organes et l’arrêt des soins’, écrit David Rodriguez-Arias."
(Emmanuelle Grand, Christian Hervé, Grégoire Moutel : "Les éléments du corps humain, la personne et la médecine", Editions de l’Harmattan, 2005).

En 2004, le Professeur Bernard Debré avait expliqué que le clonage thérapeutique constituait l’avenir des greffes, car lui seul permettrait de supprimer un jour le douloureux problème de la pénurie de greffons :

"(...) personne ne prend vraiment la peine d’expliquer au grand public que
bien des cas aujourd’hui désespérés pourraient ne plus l’être si l’on autorisait
les recherches sur le clonage humain ! Que cet enfant, ce parent, cet ami, que
nous voyons s’éteindre, nous pourrions aussi bien le voir reprendre vie, pour
peu que quelques vérités élémentaires s’imposent enfin...La première de toutes
est que le clonage reproductif, dont on ne discerne ni l’avenir ni l’utilité
s’agissant de l’Homme - les dictatures et les fanatismes religieux ont-ils
jamais eu besoin de cela pour créer, à leur convenance, des hordes fanatisées
partant au supplice dans l’espoir d’un paradis ? - n’est pas le clonage
thérapeutique. La seconde, c’est que ce dernier, et lui seul, peut un jour
parvenir à régler totalement la question des greffes d’organes, matière à la
fois compliquée, à cause des rejets, et douloureuse, en raison du manque
chronique... d’organes à greffer ! (...) Tel est l’aspect fondamental de la
recherche sur le clonage thérapeutique : achever de percer le mystère de la
spécialisation cellulaire en apprenant à repérer, à identifier, à sérier, ces
véritables ’anges gardiens’, pour mieux les inciter, le cas échéant, à
’redémarrer’ vers la construction d’un organe complet. Un organe parfaitement
sain qui deviendrait le nôtre, et serait ainsi greffable sans danger ! De
nombreuses personnalités scientifiques, dont quatre prix Nobel, réclament
l’ouverture de ce champ de recherche inespéré. Pour l’instant sans succès. Alors
que, dans le même temps, on réfléchit à autoriser l’euthanasie sur des personnes
en fin de vie, malades certes, mais cependant bien vivantes ! N’est ce pas ce
qui s’appelle marcher sur la tête ?"
(Professeur Bernard Debré : "Nous t’avons tant aimé. L’euthanasie, l’impossible loi". Editions du Cherche-Midi, 2004.)
Ce plaidoyer en faveur du clonage thérapeutique, que le Professeur Debré poursuivra dans son livre intitulé "La Revanche du serpent ou la fin de l’homo sapiens" (fin 2005), sera entendu, après un certain retard à l’allumage :

"Le décret d’application relatif à la recherche sur l’embryon et sur les
cellules embryonnaires a été publiée le 6 février 2006. En juin 2006, six
équipes de biologistes travaillant dans des structures publiques ont obtenu de
l’Agence de la biomédecine l’autorisation de mener des recherches sur les
cellules souches d’embryons humains. Sur ces six équipes, cinq sont de l’Inserm
et de l’Institut Pasteur et travailleront sur des lignées de cellules souches
embryonnaires importées. Pour la première fois, une équipe (codirigée par Marc
Peschanski et Stéphane Viville) tentera sur le territoire national de créer à
partir d’embryons humains des lignées de cellules souches."
(Source :http://www.admi.net/jo/20060207/SANP0524383D.html)

Dans la lettre citée plus haut (l’appel des parents de Mathilde), le terme "sauver" est récurrent : "seule une greffe de cœur pourra (...) sauver" cette petite fille. Faut-il rappeler que "l’espérance de vie d’un enfant transplanté ne rejoint pas celle d’un enfant normal " ?
(source : http://ethictransplantation.blogspot.com/2006/01/greffe-du-coeur-dun-enfant-donneur-en_05.html).
Dans les faits, il n’est pas rare que le terme "sauver" se situe davantage du côté du prolongement de la maladie que du côté de la rédemption miraculeuse (55 à 60 % de survie à 5 ans, source : INSERM : "Les limites de la pratique des prélèvements sur personnes décédées", Dr. MD Besse, 03/02/2004).

Demander à ce que les greffes soient déclarées grande cause nationale, n’est-ce pas mettre le gouvernement en demeure de résoudre des problèmes qui ne sont pas de son ressort, faute de quoi le recours aux solutions alternatives (le trafic d’organes) se trouverait justifié (seul le gouvernement incriminé en porterait la responsabilité) ? Proclamer les greffes grande cause nationale, c’est jeter de la poudre aux yeux des usagers de la santé, en leur faisant croire que le gouvernement a les moyens de remédier aux problèmes de pénurie de greffons, alors qu’on entrevoit déjà les effets pervers de ce choix politique : la porte ouverte au trafic d’organes : tant que le gouvernement "ne fera pas son devoir", les patients en attente de greffe se tourneront vers des "solutions alternatives". Lesquelles solutions pointent vers le trafic d’organes et la libéralisation du don d’organes, avec un marché fixant le prix des greffons. C’est déjà le cas en Allemagne - où les cœurs prélevés peuvent être transformés en "médicaments" commercialisables, c’est ainsi que des aortes peuvent être commercialisées, des banques de tissus et d’organes peuvent devenir profitables - ou encore en Espagne, où les services hospitaliers de coordination des transplantations sont indirectement autorisés à rémunérer les familles de donneurs, puisque ces services de coordination sont directement financés par l’Etat qui les incite financièrement à mettre un plus grand nombre de donneurs "décédés" à disposition... Or rappelons cette évidence : la pénurie d’organes, douloureux problème universel, n’épargne ni l’Espagne ni l’Allemagne. Aucun pays n’a pu, à aucun moment, résoudre la pénurie de greffons. Pas même en prélevant les organes des condamnés à mort en Chine... Si aucune solution n’a jamais pu être trouvée, c’est peut-être qu’elle n’existe pas ? Peut-on déclarer grande cause nationale un problème qui n’a jamais trouvé de solution nulle part - celui de la pénurie des greffons ?

Une grande cause humaniste - qui rappelle à tout instant que les greffes, celles qui font gagner des années de vie à des patients dont le pronostic vital était bien plus pessimiste avant l’opération, constituent un miracle de solidarité humaine, une conjonction exceptionnelle de talents, de chance, un tour de force sur le plan logistique, humain et matériel - est-elle reproductible à l’infini ? Les insurmontables problèmes qui suivent la transplantation comme une ombre montrent bien que l’on ne saurait répondre à une telle question par l’affirmative. Prétendre le contraire, c’est faire croire et vouloir faire croire que les bébés naissent dans les choux, c’est jeter de l’huile sur le feu entretenu par ce malentendu aux conséquences gravissimes dont parlait le Professeur Debré. C’est faire du chirurgien acteur des transplantations un pompier pyromane. Encourager le don d’organes s’avère paradoxal. Le Bulletin bibliographique de l’espace de réflexion éthique N°15 (05/2007) présente un article de Guy et Françoise Le Gall : "Rappel de la législation relative aux prélèvements d’organes et quelques questions éthiques" ("Revue : médecine et droit", 04/07, N° 83, p.50-55). Cet article évoque les problèmes qui peuvent naître d’une logique d’augmentation des dons.
Les familles confrontées au don d’organes doivent choisir entre l’accompagnement de leur proche mourant et l’autorisation du prélèvement des organes de ce mourant afin d’aider d’autres patients, qui sont pour eux de parfaits inconnus. Cette question du choix est toujours surréaliste, souvent inhumaine. Un article scientifique américain de mai 2007, concernant les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté", rend compte du suivi de nombreuses familles confrontées au don d’organes, ces familles ayant accepté ou refusé le prélèvement des organes de leur proche mourant :
“‘Non-Heart-Beating,’ or ‘Cardiac Death,’ Organ Donation : Why We Should Care” - In : Journal of Hospital Medicine 2007 ; 2(5):324-334 :
(lien : http://ethictransplantation.blogspot.com/2007/10/non-heart-beating-or-cardiac-death.html) :

"The President’s Council for Bioethics has also warned that NHBOD
can transform EOL care from a ’peaceful dignified death’ into a profanely
’high-tech death’ experience for donors’ families. Several aspects of
medical care that are neither palliative nor beneficial are performed for
donor management for NHBOD and can explain the feared transformation of the
death experience."
NHBOD : Non-heart-beating organ donation (prélèvements d’organes sur donneur "à cœur arrêté")
EOL care : End-of-life care (soins de fin de vie, soins palliatifs)

On voit que les deuils pathologiques du côté des familles confrontées au don d’organes ne sont pas exceptionnels. Une mère ayant autorisé le prélèvement des organes de son fils en état de mort encéphalique a dit avoir eu l’impression que "tout avait été orchestré pour obtenir son consentement au prélèvement des organes" de son fils. Des années plus tard, cette mère se reprochait d’avoir "abandonné son fils au pire moment de sa courte existence"...
Une promotion à tout crin des transplantations d’organes est donc à l’origine de deuils pathologiques qui se manifestent des deux côtés : côté donneur comme côté receveur, que donneur et receveur aient effectivement joué ce rôle ou qu’ils y aient été confrontés sans l’avoir joué (un donneur "décédé" pour lequel les proches ont refusé le prélèvement d’organes ; un patient décédé en attente de greffe).

Qu’il me soit permis de rappeler ici une évidence, qui, pour être en relation directe avec le taux de refus des prélèvements d’organes sur donneurs "décédés", n’en est pas moins soigneusement passée sous silence dans le discours public : les états de mort qui permettent les prélèvements d’organes constituent des formes de mort dites "équivoques" (état de "mort encéphalique" ou patients "décédés présentant un arrêt cardiaque et respiratoire persistant"). L’état de mort dit "univoque" ne permet, quant à lui, aucun prélèvement d’organes. Techniquement, les patients "décédés" potentiels donneurs d’organes sont soit maintenus en vie artificielle, soit réanimés, pour mourir au moment du prélèvement de leurs organes. Imaginer que ces patients réanimés ou maintenus en vie artificielle sont de simples pourvoyeurs d’organes et non des patients en fin de vie, que l’on doit protéger de "l’acharnement thérapeutique déraisonnable" (comme préconisé par la loi Léonetti d’avril 2005, dite "loi sur la fin de vie") n’est pas chose aisée. En effet, ces potentiels donneurs font inévitablement l’objet d’un "acharnement thérapeutique déraisonnable", dans le but de conserver leurs organes et de transformer ces derniers en greffons viables (but "éthique", "altruiste"). Cette "technicisation de l’agonie" (Dr. Andronikof) au service des prélèvements d’organes est cause de deuils pathologiques chez bien des familles confrontées au don d’organes, qui redoutent la "rapacité" des équipes médicales. Cette technicisation prend alors la connotation d’une profanation, d’une transgression pour ces familles. Est-il besoin d’être Saint-Augustin, Père de l’Eglise, pour dire : "Tout n’est pas profitable" ?...

Ces derniers développements posent la question de la faisabilité et de la justification, sur le plan déontologique, d’une systématisation de la promotion du don d’organes (don systématisé et systématique). Faut-il organiser un système de recyclage d’un individu à l’autre ? Quelles sont les limites d’un système de récupération de bouts d’hommes pour soigner l’homme ? Les limites techniques, conjoncturelles (pénurie de greffons), scientifiques (controverses), financières (l’allongement de la durée de vie entraîne une augmentation du besoin en greffons, d’où l’aggravation de la pénurie certes, mais aussi l’augmentation du coût des greffes, que la Sécurité Sociale ne pourra pas supporter) - toutes ces limites rendent le problème des transplantations extraordinairement complexe. Trop pour faire du don d’organes une cause nationale ? Qui pourra encore se payer une greffe en 2050 ? C’est la question que posent les auteurs du documentaire « Les Fabricants de cœur » (Arte, 27/02/2007).
Lien : http://ethictransplantation.blogspot.com/2007/03/documentaire-les-fabricants-de-curs.html

Lire cet article, ainsi que les réactions et commentaires sur AgoraVox, le média citoyen :
==> cliquer ici.

Claire Boileau : "Dans le dédale du don d'organes"

Je prépare actuellement un article sur le livre de Claire Boileau : "Dans le dédale du don d'organes : le cheminement de l'ethnologue", Edition des Archives Contemporaines, 07/2002.
==> Lien vers ce livre sur Amazon.fr

Présentation de l'éditeur
Qui n'a pas entendu parler de la pénurie de greffons ? Les Français manqueraient-ils de cœur au point de compromettre le succès des greffes ? Et si le manque de greffons s'articulait en fait autour du prélèvement d'organes et des inquiétudes qu'il suscite, donc en amont de la greffe ? Cet ouvrage n'est pas un réquisitoire et l'auteur ne vous dira pas " ce qu'il faut choisir " : l'ethnologue porte son regard ailleurs, sur l'envers de la greffe et ce que nous ne voulons habituellement ni voir ni savoir. C'est bien là, au moment d'un prélèvement d'organes, que surgissent nos interrogations les plus intimes : celles de nos chairs, de nos représentations de la mort et du corps ; il laisse désemparées les familles à qui l'on demande l'autorisation de prélever les organes d'un être cher comme il renvoie les soignants à de terribles dilemmes. Qui mieux que l'ethnologue pouvait révéler la nature même de ces réticences ?
A l'heure où les biotechnologies sont de plus en plus souvent sollicitées pour soigner, réparer ou remplacer l'organisme défaillant, il est plus que temps de s'interroger sur le sens profond de ces nouveaux usages dont les enjeux débordent largement leur cadre technologique.

Biographie de l'auteur
Après une formation et une pratique infirmière, Claire Boileau s'est tournée vers l'anthropologie du corps, de la mort et du don. Elle est actuellement anthropologue, chercheur associé au Laboratoire "Sociétés, santé, développement" - CNRS (Université de Bordeaux II). Elle a également été membre du Conseil Médical et Scientifique de l'Etablissement Français des Greffes.

Prélèvements « à cœur arrêté » : controverses et mises à jour

Prélèvements « à cœur arrêté » : controverses et mises à jour, Enjeux d’une médiation éthique
Un acteur des transplantations affirmait récemment, lors d’un congrès rassemblant des spécialistes de la réanimation : "les prélèvements ‘à cœur arrêté’ rencontrent une large adhésion de la part de la société ". Cette affirmation pourrait paraître paradoxale, puisqu’à l’heure actuelle, aucun discours public sur les prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" n’a été mis en place. Comment le consentement (ou le refus) éclairé au don de ses organes à sa mort, inscrit dans la loi, va-t-il pouvoir être recueilli auprès d’un grand public qui, tout en ignorant tout ou presque des prélèvements "à cœur arrêté", est sans cesse sollicité afin de prendre position pour ou contre le don de ses organes à sa mort ?

Dans un esprit de médiation éthique, il nous est apparu indispensable que les usagers de la santé, et non les seuls acteurs des transplantations, puissent bénéficier d’une information objective, c’est-à dire affranchie de l’obligation de la promotion du don d’organes, au sujet des prélèvements dits "à cœur arrêté".

Quels sont les enjeux de cette médiation éthique ?

==> Prélèvements "à cœur arrêté" : controverses et mises à jour (PDF, 11 pages, 240 Ko)

Recovery of transplantable organs after cardiac or circulatory death: Transforming the paradigm for the ethics of organ donation

Abstract
"Organ donation after cardiac or circulatory death (DCD) has been introduced to increase the supply of transplantable organs. In this paper, we argue that the recovery of viable organs useful for transplantation in DCD is not compatible with the dead donor rule and we explain the consequential ethical and legal ramifications. We also outline serious deficiencies in the current consent process for DCD with respect to disclosure of necessary elements for voluntary informed decision making and respect for the donor's autonomy. We compare two alternative proposals for increasing organ donation consent in society: presumed consent and mandated choice. We conclude that proceeding with the recovery of transplantable organs from decedents requires a paradigm change in the ethics of organ donation. The paradigm change to ensure the legitimacy of DCD practice must include:
(1) societal agreement on abandonment of the dead donor rule
(2) legislative revisions reflecting abandonment of the dead donor rule
(3) requirement of mandated choice to facilitate individual participation in organ donation and to ensure that decisions to participate are made in compliance with the societal values of respect for autonomy and self-determination."

Background

"Medical and pharmacologic advancements have made it possible to transplant organs successfully and thereby to save the lives of many persons who otherwise would die from irreversible end-stage organ disease. The greatly enhanced technical ability to transplant organs has also led to an ever-increasing need for transplantable organs. The explosive growth in the demand for and the marginal increase in the supply of transplantable organs have together been characterized as an 'evolving national health care crisis'. In fact, organ donation rates nationally have changed little in the past 15 years, whereas the need for donated organs has grown 5 times faster than the number of available cadaveric organs. It is therefore no surprise that the transplantation community and society as a whole now consider balancing the demand for and the supply of transplantable organs as one of their biggest challenges.

The continually increasing need for organs led to the reintroduction of the principle of donation after cardiac or circulatory death (DCD) in the early 1990s with the Pittsburgh protocol to complement already available organ procurement from brain-dead persons. A new federal mandate requires hospitals as of January 2007 to design policies and procedures for organ procurement in DCD to increase the rate of organ donation and recovery from decedents to 75% or greater.

However, DCD is controversial because of medical, ethical, and legal uncertainties about the premise that donors are indeed dead before their organs are procured. In this article, we contend that the recovery of viable organs useful for transplantation in DCD is not compatible with the dead donor rule and we explain the ethical and legal ramifications of DCD. We also examine the current process of consent for organ donation and whether it includes the necessary elements for voluntary informed consent (i.e., the full disclosure of information relevant to decision making and respect for the person's autonomy). We will contrast the ethical aspects of two alternative proposals for increasing donation consent in society: presumed consent and mandated choice. Finally, we will conclude by positing that in order for the current principle of DCD to proceed with recovery of transplantable organs from decedents, a paradigm change in the ethics of organ donation is necessary. The paradigm change to ensure the legitimacy of DCD practice must include (1) societal agreement on abandonment of the dead donor rule, (2) legislative revisions reflecting abandonment of the dead donor rule, and (3) the requirement of mandated choice to facilitate individual participation in organ donation and to ensure that DCD is in compliance with the societal values of respect for autonomy and self-determination."

DCD and the dead donor rule
"The criteria for determining death play a prominent role in the acceptability of DCD. The recovery of viable organs for successful transplantation must be achieved with the donor already dead at the time of procurement in order to comply with the dead donor rule. Whereas some have considered a person dead after 2 minutes of apnea, unresponsiveness, and absent arterial pulse, the Institute of Medicine recommended waiting for 5 minutes of absent consciousness, respiration, and mechanical pump function of the heart (zero pulse pressure through arterial catheter monitoring), irrespective of the presence of electric activity of the heart (evident on electrocardiographic monitoring). In 2001, the American College as well as the Society of Critical Care Medicine concluded in a position statement that a waiting period of either 2 minutes or 5 minutes was physiologically and ethically equivalent and therefore either was an acceptable timeline for beginning the process of organ retrieval. Waiting for longer than 5 minutes can cause warm ischemia and detrimentally affect the quality of procured organs and impair their suitability for transplantation. However, critics have argued more than a decade ago that the waiting time to determine death by respiratory and circulatory criteria is based on insufficient scientific evidence. The spontaneous return of circulation and respiration (i.e., the Lazarus phenomenon or autoresuscitation) has been reported to occur in humans as long as 10 minutes after cessation of circulation and respiration. Autoresuscitation appears to validate previous concerns that viable organs may be procured from persons who are in the process of dying yet are not truly dead.

According to the Uniform Determination of Death Act (UDDA) of 1981, a person is determined dead after having sustained either irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions or irreversible cessation of all brain function, including that of the brain stem, and the determination of death must be made in accordance with accepted medical standards. The President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research defined the statute for the determination of death so that 'Death is a Single Phenomenon'. The statute is intended to address the question 'how, given medical advances in cardiopulmonary support, can the evidence that death has occurred be obtained and recognized'. The President's Commission defined the cessation of circulation to be irreversible for death determination '[i]f deprived of blood flow for at least 10–15 minutes, the brain, including the brainstem, will completely cease functioning. A 4–6 minute loss of blood flow – caused by, for example, cardiac arrest – typically damages the cerebral cortex permanently, while the relatively more resistant brainstem may continue to function.'

The challenge in determining death for organ procurement is twofold:

(1) the use of an arbitrary set of criteria and time frames to define irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions without evidence of the uniformity for death determination and
(2) the variability of the criteria used by different institutions for organ procurement protocols.

The notion of irreversibility of cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions has been a contentious medical and ethical issue. Tomlinson proposed a definition of irreversibility as 'a requirement that arises only at the level of the criteria for the determination of death, rather than at the level of the concept of death, just as beyond reasonable doubt is not a part of the concept of guilty, but instead is a requirement for the legitimate determination of guilt within a judicial system.'. The requirement for irreversibility therefore depends on the context in which, and the purposes for which, the concept of death is being used. The notion of irreversibility is commonly understood as meaning either that the heart cannot be restarted spontaneously (a weaker construal) or that the heart cannot be restarted despite standard cardiopulmonary resuscitation (a stronger construal). The stronger construal of irreversibility as meaning 'can never be reversed' implies in its extreme that at no time can organ procurement ever be permissible because future possibilities of resuscitation can never be fully ruled out. In practical terms, the weaker definition of 'not reversible now' implies that a person is considered irreversibly dead based on that person's moral choice to forego resuscitative interventions; thus, as long as the probability of autoresuscitation is negligible, the dead donor rule is not violated. On the basis of that argument, the notion of irreversibility depends on the person's choice to forego resuscitative interventions after spontaneous cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions. However, the argument that irreversibility can be understood as a moral choice is flawed. First, the issue is not whether there are good reasons not to resuscitate a person but whether the person is truly dead. Second, resuscitative interventions are performed during the procurement process to keep organs viable for transplantation after the cessation of vital functions. The use of artificial cardiopulmonary bypass machines, external mechanical cardiac compression devices, and reinflation of the lungs to preserve organs for procurement also results in the resuscitation of the heart and the brain after the formal declaration of death. Resuscitation of the brain with a return of consciousness is particularly problematic because the Institute of Medicine announced in its 2006 report that expansion of the organ donor pool by procuring organs from living persons with normal brain function who sustain sudden cardiac death is morally acceptable.

Longer than 10 minutes of absent circulation is required for irreversible cessation of the entire human brain, including brain stem function. The administration of medications to suppress heart and brain functions is therefore required when the procurement process begins within 5 minutes of cessation of circulation.

The use of resuscitative methods and medications to suppress heart and brain functions during organ procurement raises a host of additional ethical and legal questions. Organ donors consent to the withholding of all resuscitative interventions after cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions through a do-not-resuscitate (DNR) directive. Under such conditions, the use of resuscitative methods for organ procurement violates not only the dead donor rule but also the person's health directives. The strong probability of a return of heart and brain functions during procurement also means that the act of organ removal is the immediate and proximate cause of death for that person.

The need for criteria to sharpen 'the indeterminate boundary between life and death' for death determination has been widely recognized. The dependence on both circulatory and respiratory criteria only for the determination of death in DCD is problematic and conceptually inconsistent because of

(1) there is a likelihood of spontaneous reversibility of circulatory and respiratory functions when organ procurement begins, and
(2) the possibility for the brain to recover function long after circulatory arrest, particularly when artificial circulation is used for organ procurement. Therefore, the practice of DCD conflates a prognosis of death with a diagnosis of death. The application of criteria for irreversible cessation of neurologic, circulatory and respiratory functions requires a waiting time well in excess of 10 minutes to sharpen the determination of death for organ procurement. However, that waiting time can also make it more difficult to recover viable organs for transplantation. The simultaneous determination of total cessation of the activity of the entire brain, including the brain stem, is required for the determination of death when respiration and circulation are artificially supported during organ procurement. Capron and Kass emphasized in the President's Commission when defining death 'A person will be considered dead if in the announced opinion of a physician, based on ordinary standards of medical practice, he has experienced an irreversible cessation of respiratory and circulatory functions, or in the event that artificial means of support preclude a determination that these functions have ceased, he has experienced an irreversible cessation of total brain functions'. "

The dead donor rule and the law
"DCD has been recommended on the basis of the utilitarian rationale of maximizing the number of organ transplants in order to save more lives. This utilitarian approach has also provided implicit justification for manipulation of some aspects of the death process. Intervention has been justified not only in the dying process but also in defining the word dead. The uncertainty of the uniformity of determination of death in DCD has legal implications. The act of procurement or the removal of organs from persons who may still be in the process of dying but who are labeled as being dead, becomes the direct and proximate cause of death or of 'killing' rather than the natural illness itself. Medically redefining death arbitrarily to permit DCD for organ procurement has been a necessary prerequisite for the circumvention of homicide law. Declaration of death or calling someone dead takes the burden off procurement personnel and provides the appearance that it is acceptable to remove organs under such conditions without being found guilty of murder. The purposeful manipulation of the criteria for the determination of death serves the desired goal of increasing the opportunities for procurement of transplantable organs, but it also represents a knowing gerrymandering of the existing legal definition. The President's Commission indicated in the 1981 report on defining death that the UDDA is intended to aid in the process of recognition and providing a legal standard to distinguish the dead from the dying and, ought not to reinforce the misimpression that there are different 'kinds' of death, defined for different purposes, and hence that some people are more 'dead' than others. An argument can be made that a person's consent or permission for organ donation can legitimize this intervention, as with any other medical procedure with potential risk of death. However, that argument transgresses the legal limits of autonomy, because no person can consent to his or her own killing. The ban on assisted suicide, regardless of a person's wishes, reaffirms that society has a consolidated interest in preserving life. In the United States (U.S.), physician-assisted suicide is legalized only in the State of Oregon. "

Problems with consent for organ donation
"Organ procurement organizations (OPOs) are the designated requesters for organ donation. Hospitals are required to notify OPOs of all imminent deaths before withdrawal of ventilator support to allow OPO representatives to initiate independent discussion of consent for organ donation with surrogates. The OPOs are private organizations under government contract with Medicare and Medicaid Services to coordinate deceased organ procurement. Each OPO has significant financial incentives for maximizing organs recovery through consent for donation from hospitals located within the donation service area. The Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative has set three top-level goals for each OPO to achieve:

1) a 75% or higher organ donation (or conversion) rate from regional hospitals,
2) 3.75 (or greater) organs transplanted per organ donor and
3) DCD to account for 10% (or greater) of donation service area's deceased donors, without a decrease in brain dead donors. The successful compliance with the set goals are required for each OPO to maintain active certification and renewal of contract with Medicare for payment for services provided in a donation service area. Additional financial incentives for the OPO to aggressively purse organ donation in Medicare approved hospitals include reimbursement for actual donors, financial returns on local transplant activity solely supported by local donor activity and Medicare incentives for local organ donation activity.

Obtaining consent is considered one of the guiding principles that provide moral validation of organ transplant programs. Consent for organ donation can be registered and documented in several ways. The donor registry is an online electronic database for accessing donor consent information and it is readily available to OPO personnel. In contrast, donor consent documented on driver's licenses, donor cards, or advanced directives may not be available to clinicians when donation or procurement decisions must be made. Consent for organ donation is obtained in two different situations. The first situation is to acquire consent from healthy persons for future organ donation. It is generally achieved by inviting members of the public to complete donor cards (e.g., as part of a driver's license application) providing general consent for organ donation or to consent to organ donation by signing up on a state registry when they visit an OPO Web site. The second situation occurs when consent is obtained from a surrogate decision maker for a brain-dead person or a person for whom death is imminent and who has not expressed intent for organ donation through a driver's license, a donor card or donor registry.

Studies show that half of the families who are asked to consider donation after a relative's death refuse consent. It should therefore come as no surprise that in addition to educating the public, the Institute of Medicine Committee on Increasing Rates of Organ Donation has identified among its primary objectives an increase in the number of opportunities for people to record the decision to donate and the enhancement of donor registries to ensure full access to and sharing of donor registration data.

Requiring consent is consistent with one of the cornerstones of medicine and bioethics: respect for individual autonomy. Among other things, the process of obtaining consent must include the provision of an appropriate quantity and quality of information so that the person can make an informed decision. Currently, the consent for DCD is requested with disclosure of similar information as with brain-death donation. Given the medical and ethical uncertainties surrounding DCD, its consent process should be expected to be different from that used in brain-death donation. The differences between the two types of organ donation with regard to timing and the nature of the procurement procedure, nonbeneficial interventions, and trade-offs in end-of-life care are not often clarified to potential donors or surrogate decision makers at the time of consent. DCD also exposes donors to the risk of failing to die within the allotted time frame for successful organ procurement after the performance of predonation procedures.

Considering that actual donation or procurement processes differ according to the death criteria, one might expect the consent process to include details about the various death scenarios. In 2006, Woien et al examined the quality and quantity of information about consent that is disclosed to the public and to potential organ donors on OPO Web sites. The information content about relevant aspects of medical interventions, procedures, protocols and changes to the quality of end-of-life care was found to be deficient because it was focused primarily on the encouragement and reinforcement of consent to donation. This lack of disclosure on OPO Web sites and in online consent documentation raises doubts about whether organ donors actually receive and understand the pertinent information necessary to making an informed decision about whether to participate in deceased organ donation. The lack of detailed and accurate disclosure violates the tenet of informed consent and abuses the public's trust in the deceased organ donation system.

The medical community is expected to be transparent and to fully inform the public about the different donation practices and their implications. Yet, disclosing more detailed information about organ donation to the general public may very well result in a decrease in donor registrations. Suggestions that the organ supply shortage is a health care crisis may also have a detrimental effect by exacerbating public fears and by fueling excessive worry or speculation that procurement decisions may ultimately go beyond socially accepted thresholds. The Institute of Medicine has proposed changes in the consent format as a way to increase the organ donation rate in the community while also reducing the risk of increased public fear. The explicit or express consent of competent adults or surrogate decision makers is the current standard for organ donation consent. Other consent options include the presumed consent, conscription (sometimes referred to as routine removal) or mandated choice."

Presumed consent
"Presumed consent means either implied consent inferred from other actions or tacit consent that constitutes consent in the absence of explicit dissent. Presumed consent within the context of organ donation implies a default position of donation for those persons who do not take action to dissent (opting out). The switch from explicit consent to implicit presumed consent has been advocated as an efficient method to increase the supply of transplantable organs.

The ethical justification commonly given for a switch to presumed consent is twofold. First, polls show that about 69% of Americans are 'very likely' or 'somewhat likely' to grant permission to have their organs harvested after death, which suggests broad public support. However, there has always been a gap between people's perceived attitudes in polls on organ donation and what they do in practice. Perhaps this is not simply a refection of knowledge but of personal experiences and beliefs. Also in a subsequent national survey of organ and tissue donation attitudes and behaviors (conducted by the Gallup Organization and prepared for the Division of Transplantation Health resources and Services Administration), most people either 'opposed' (26.7%) or 'strongly opposed' (30.1%) presumed consent. In the same survey, about 3 in 10 reported that they would opt-out of a presumed consent approach. Second, as some have argued, deceased organ donation should be considered a duty rather than an act of charity. Hester postulated that 'deciding not to release our organs for transplantation would constitute a serious moral wrong' in light of the desperate need for transplantable organs.

Presumed consent certainly poses a challenge to the principle of protecting a person's right to fully informed agreement (consent), and its moral justification therefore falls short. First, the issue of a moral obligation to donate organs at death is still subject to debate; a public discourse on this topic has not yet taken place. Second, access to health care including organ transplantation services is not universal. Data released in August 2006 by the U.S. Census Bureau showed that more than 46.8 million people are uninsured and 24.4% of those earned less than $25,000, an unknown number of people had limited health care coverage, and 12.6% of the U.S. population lived below the poverty margin. As the erosion of employer-based health insurance continues, the numbers of underinsured and uninsured persons are likely to increase. In addition, 82% of kidney recipients are white which leads one to speculate that there may be racial discrepancy in organ allocation. Third, the duties of relevant stakeholders in health care remain poorly defined. The question of who is responsible for what in health care has yet to be answered, which is even more troubling in light of the fact that health care in the 21st century is more commonly understood solely in terms of a commodity operating in a self-regulating free-market environment. How complex social interactions are to be arranged is a subject of rational discourse for which every participant should assume responsibility and be held accountable.

Widespread public education and clear, easy and transparent ways for persons to register dissent are requirements for an ethically acceptable presumed consent policy. Considering that the current process of donation consent is deficient in its provision of basic information about organ donation and that there is an absence of established social practices that would warrant the presumption of consent for organ donation, the justification is lacking for a switch from express to presumed consent in the United States.

Conscription, also referred to as mandatory donation, is the routine postmortem removal of organs for transplantation. As such, it presupposes society's right of access to the organs of any deceased person. Such a right would rest either on the claim that society 'owns' the body of the deceased or on the premise of an enforceable moral duty all of us as humans have to allow postmortem organ retrieval. In the U.S., the government does not claim complete authority over the disposition of the bodies of the deceased. Some states in the U.S. have even interpreted the right of a person or family to decide whether to donate organs as an interest sufficient to endow some rights to the corpse that cannot be disregarded without due process. Such laws have assigned a property interest in the body to the next of kin. Conscription would depart from this legal principle as well as from the norm of expressed consent.

Although the routine removal of organs after death is inconsistent with current U.S. federal and state laws, some proponents postulate the appropriateness of conscription on practical and ethical grounds. Practical arguments include the fact that people with organ failure are dying daily because of the short supply of transplantable organs and that many usable organs are never made available, most commonly because of family refusal. Conscription would override family refusal for donation and produce an efficient rate of deceased organ recovery almost close to 100%. Conscription would eliminate the need for costly public education programs, training of requesters, and maintenance of donor registries; it might also alleviate concern about abuse or possible commodification of the human body. The duty-based justification for conscription fails, however, because organ transplantation practices are inconsistent with the requirement of universality. Not everyone is included in a fair system that is mutually beneficial. Conscription would maximize organ recovery but would do so to the detriment of respect for personal autonomy and accepted societal norms. It would also violate the religious values of some persons for the body to not be buried whole."

Mandated choice
"The second consent option is that of mandated choice. Mandated choice would require all adult persons in the community to consider organ donation and to document their decision. All competent adults would be required to decide in advance to agree to organ donation or to refuse organ donation, and their wishes would be considered legally binding (unless they had a documented change of mind before actually dying). Mandated choice would preserve altruism and the voluntary nature of donation, and as such proponents consider it to be consistent with the principle of respect for autonomy. Opponents of mandated choice postulate that it is unacceptable in a libertarian society to force people to make choices and that mandated choice is coercive and an intrusion on privacy. Concerns have also been raised that mandated choice would disallow consideration of the views of the family.

With the current view of the shortage of transplantable organs identified by many people as a health care crisis, one might argue that neither a mandate to make an autonomous prospective decision about organ donation nor the expectation of a family's compliance with the wishes of the deceased is unreasonable. A similar justification can be made about the intrusion of privacy associated with mandated choice. However, mandated choice would require full disclosure of relevant unbiased information about all aspects of organ procurement that, in turn, constitutes informed consent. The importance of public education in mandated choice is illustrated by the failure of a state initiative in Texas. In 1991, Texas enacted a law requiring citizens to make a 'yes' or 'no' choice about organ donation when they renewed their driver's license. The law had to be repealed in 1997 because the implementation of the mandatory choice resulted in a refusal rate of 80%. This high rate of refusal was attributed to the lack of public education about organ donation. It is therefore of great concern that OPOs today have focused their efforts on convincing members of the public to become organ donors rather than on providing adequate unbiased information and education about organ donation. A 2006 report from the Institute of Medicine suggested that optimal public education would be cost prohibitive and labor intensive."

Paradigm transformation of organ donation ethics
"There is growing doubt among scholars and medical practitioners that DCD can comply with the principles on which it was introduced into society as an ethically acceptable practice. We have highlighted several concerns indicating that the current DCD practice not only violates the dead donor rule but also puts the moral legitimacy of consent for donation in question. Unless the current DCD practice is reevaluated, the erosion of public trust and damage to the integrity of the medical profession are likely to develop over time. To avoid these negative consequences, we are faced with implementing any or all of three strategic options. The first strategy would be to discontinue DCD and instead focus on reducing the demand for transplantable organs by promoting healthy lifestyles (i.e., primary and secondary prevention programs for chronic diseases such as diabetes and hypertension). This strategy might decrease the future incidence of end-stage organ disease and the resulting need for transplantation; however, it would not resolve the current imbalance between the supply of and the demand for organs. The second strategy would be to revise the uniform definition of death to allow the definition of 'dead' to be applied to dying persons so that the recovery of transplantable organs from DCD can be continued in an ethical and legal manner. Bernat, for instance, has argued for a change in the standard determination of death that would substitute 'permanence' for 'irreversibility' and thereby permit the classification of dying persons as truly dead. Bernat's proposal to change the death determination implicitly acknowledges that the current DCD practice is inconsistent with the dead donor rule. Bernat justifies violation of the dead donor rule and there is no need to distinguish between the 'dying' and the 'dead' for the purpose of organ procurement for transplantation. The justification put forward by Bernat conflicts with the President's Commission views on when and how the death statute is applied 'to distinguish the dead from the dying' and to prevent 'the mistaken impression that a special definition of death needs to be applied to organ transplantation, which is not the case' and that it 'ought not to reinforce the misimpression that there are different kinds of death, defined for different purposes, and hence that some people are [more dead] than others'.

The word 'permanence' conveys the absolute accuracy of the 'prognosis' rather than a determination or diagnosis of death. However, opponents of the criterion of absolute certainty of prognosis of death may consider as homicide its application to persons for whom the consent to withdraw artificial life support is made. Revising the UDDA in this manner would have far-reaching ethical implications not only for society but also for criminal and homicide laws. Criminal prosecution, inheritance, taxation, treatment of cadaver, and mourning are all affected by the way society draws the dividing line between life and death. More importantly, it can violate the principle of nonmaleficence by allowing the introduction of errors in prognostication that may have a detrimental effect on end-of-life care and palliation. The third strategy would be to abandon the dead donor rule for organ procurement so that procuring organs becomes permissible during the terminally ill person's dying phase after voluntary informed consent has been obtained. The abandonment of the dead donor rule would constitute a paradigm switch in the ethics of deceased organ procurement for transplantation from donor beneficence to autonomy and nonmaleficence. Donors would be solely responsible for their decisions, and the medical community would have to comply with the do-no-harm principle at the end of life. As is the case with revising the determination of death, this paradigm switch would require changes in criminal and homicide laws to legitimize DCD legally, ethically, and medically. In addition, changing the paradigm would require public discourse about permitting autonomy-based end-of-life decisions. The preservation of a person's autonomy and the voluntary nature of the decision are fundamental for such a profound paradigm shift and, as such, they require comprehensive public education and disclosure of all relevant information. The mandated personal choice in conjunction with the paradigm shift would protect an individual's right to agree or refuse and thereby would eliminate coercion in the organ donation consent process with minimal infringement on privacy. Within this context, mandated choice restores the public trust and eliminates the individual's fear of manipulation of the dying and death process for the intent of organ procurement. Mandated choice is compatible with the principle of respect for individual autonomy and decision making, and it does not require additional consent from a person's family to procure organs after death."

Conclusion
"The long-term solution for overcoming the shortage of transplantable organs is to focus on, and to broadly implement, universally accessible preventive health-care programs. For the short term, increasing the number of potential donors while also maintaining the public trust and the integrity of medicine requires public education, a consent process characterized by full disclosure of relevant information about organ donation and procurement procedures critical to the decision making about organ donation, and a switch of the ethics paradigm from beneficence to nonmaleficence and respect for individual autonomy to allow for DCD to comply with legal and ethical standards. The implementation of mandated choice for obtaining consent would appear reasonable and morally justifiable to assist with the objective of increasing the number of people who consent to organ donation after death. Ultimately, the outcome of public debate must be the decisive factor in determining the conditions under which DCD should be considered legitimate. "

Authors:
Joseph L Verheijde 1
Mohamed Y Rady 2
Joan McGregor 3

1 Department of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, Mayo Clinic Hospital, Phoenix, Arizona, USA
2 Department of Critical Care Medicine, Mayo Clinic Hospital, Phoenix, Arizona, USA
3 Department of Biomedical Ethics and Medical Humanities Program, College of Medicine-Phoenix, University of Arizona and Department of Philosophy, Arizona State University, Arizona, USA
Published: 22 May 2007

Source:
Copyright Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine (PEHM)
http://www.peh-med.com/content/2/1/8

"Non-Heart-Beating," or "Cardiac Death," Organ Donation : Why We Should Care

From Journal of Hospital Medicine
"Non-Heart-Beating," or "Cardiac Death," Organ Donation : Why We Should Care - Posted 10/05/2007

Mohamed Y. Rady, MD, PhD, FRCS (Eng.), FRCP (UK), FCCM, (1) Joseph L. Verheijde, PhD, MBA (2) and Joan McGregor, PhD (3)

(1) Departments of Critical Care Medicine, Mayo Clinic Hospital, Mayo Clinic Arizona, Phoenix, Arizona
(2) Department of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, Mayo Clinic Hospital, Mayo Clinic Arizona, Phoenix, Arizona
(3) Bioethics, Policy, and Law Program, School of Life Sciences and Department of Philosophy, Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona

Journal of Hospital Medicine 2007;2(5):324-334.

Copyright 2007 John Wiley and Sons, Inc.

Abstract and Introduction

Abstract

"Background: Organ donation after cessation of cardiac pump activity is referred to as non-heart-beating organ donation (NHBOD). NHBOD donors can be neurologically intact; they do not fulfill the brain death criteria prior to cessation of cardiac pump activity. For hospitals to participate in NHBOD, they must comply with a newly introduced federal requirement for ICU patients whose deaths are considered imminent after withdrawal of life support. This report describes issues related to NHBOD.

Methods: A nonstructured review of selected publications and Web sites was undertaken.

Results: Scientific evidence from autoresuscitation and extracorporeal perfusion suggests that verifying cardiorespiratory arrest lasting 2-5 minutes does not uniformly comply with the dead donor rule, so that the process of organ procurement can be the irreversible event defining death in organ donors. The interest of organ procurement organizations and affiliates in maximizing recovery of transplantable organs introduces self-serving bias in gaining consent for organ donation and abandons the basic tenet of obtaining true informed consent. The impact of donor management and procurement protocols on end-of-life (EOL) care and the potential trade-off are not disclosed, raising concern about whether potential donors and their families are fully informed before consenting to donation.

Conclusions: The use of comprehensive quality indicators for EOL care can determine the impact of NHBOD on care offered to donors and the effects on families and health care providers. Detailed evaluation of NHBOD will enable thepublic to make informed decisions about participating in this type of organ donation."

Introduction
"In April 2003 the Health Resources and Services Administration of the U.S. Department of Health & Human Services (DHHS) announced the formation of the Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative (ODBC).[1] The Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative created 58 national donation service areas (DSAs) to organize the transplant community across the United States. Each of the 58 organ procurement organizations (OPOs) is joined to a regional transplant center or centers and donor hospitals to form a DSA. The ODBC's goal is to achieve a cadaveric organ donation rate of 75% or higher from hospitals within each DSA.[2]

A requirement for organ donation from patients facing imminent or cardiac death has been introduced to increase the supply of transplantable organs and shorten the waiting time for transplantation candidates.[3–5] This type of organ donation represents a significant source of organs required for future expansion of trans plantation practice in the United States. The requirement for donation in imminent or cardiac death is implemented through the collaboration of the Advisory Committee on Organ Transplantation of the DHHS (Table 1), the Centers for Medicare & Medicaid Services (CMS), and the Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO).[3,5–7] The organ donor pool of those facing imminent or cardiac death has also been expanded to include neurologically intact patients who may not fulfill brain death criteria before withdrawal of life support.[4,8,9]

The President's Council on Bioethics independently evaluated the issues surrounding deceased organ donation and procurement.[10] The President's Council on Bioethics has expressed major concerns about several issues pertinent to cardiac or imminent death organ donation that have not been addressed explicitly by the bodies that have made recommendations for reforming or expanding that type of organ donation in the United States. The debate on organ procurement in imminent or cardiac death has come to the forefront because of doubts about its ethical appropriateness and acceptance within the medical profession and the community at large. This review focuses on the serious issues related to organ procurement from patients facing imminent or cardiac death."

Organ Procurement and the Dead Donor Rule

"Organ procurement is only permitted when the donor is already dead (ie, the dead donor rule), and the act of organ recovery cannot have been the immediate act to cause that death.[10,11] There are 2 criteria for death as defined in the Uniform Determination of Death Act (UDDA; Table 1): an individual who has sustained irreversible cessation of either (1) circulatory and respiratory functions or (2) all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem, is considered dead and this determination of death must have been made in accordance with accepted medical standards.[12] When organs are procured from an individual in whom all brain function has ceased but normal cardiac pump activity is continuing, it is referred to as heart-beating organ donation. Organ procurement after cessation of cardiac pump activity and cardiorespiratory functions is referred to as non-heart-beating organ donation (NHBOD). Organ procurement from an individual in imminent or cardiac death is considered NHBOD.

Non-heart-beating organ donors can be neurologically intact and do not fulfill the brain death criterion prior to cessation of cardiac pump activity. In response to this dilemma, the University of Pittsburgh Medical Centre developed a protocol for donation of organs that permitted their procurement from patients who were pulseless and apneic for 2 minutes and did not fulfill brain criteria and who had previously given consent for organ donation.[13] Because it is uncertain if cessation of cardiorespiratory function is irreversible after only a short time, the Institute of Medicine (IOM) extended the time required for pulselessness and apnea from 2 to 5 minutes before permitting organ procurement.[14] Waiting longer than 5 minutes for the determination of death would compromise the quality of procured organs because of warm ischemia time and would influence the functioning of grafts in transplant recipients.

One of the pivotal assumptions for NHBOD acceptance is that 5 minutes of pulselessness and apnea eliminates the possibility that the procurement process itself could be the cause of death and fulfills the "dead donor rule."[14,15] The cardiorespiratory death criteria were derived from observations that did not evaluate delayed autoresuscitation (spontaneous return of circulation) or simultaneous cessation of brain electrical activity (as recorded in brain death).[16–18] The death criteria applied for organ procurement must also comply with the irreversibility requirement of the UDDA.[11,12]

The true incidence, temporal characteristics, and predictors of autoresuscitation in humans remain unknown because of underreporting in the literature. However, there have been case reports of autoresuscitation with return of neurologic function (also called the Lazarus phenomenon) after 10 minutes of cardiac asystole.[19,20] Maleck et al. and Adhiyaman et al. described autoresuscitation 5 minutes or longer after cardiorespiratory arrest in 44% and 50% of the published case reports, respectively.[19,20] Although cardiac asystole leads to the loss of arterial pulse pressure, circulatory arterial mean pressure is maintained in diastole by arteriolar vasomotor tone. The relaxation (diastole) phase systemic arterial to venous pressure gradient provides the perfusion pressure for vital organs and the spontaneous return of circulation after circulatory arrest.[21] It is likely that autoresuscitation occurs because of the persistence of circulatory vasomotor tone after cessation of cardiac function. The time course of systemic vascular tone after circulatory arrest has not been well characterized in humans. However, the IOM criteria did not account for the incidence of delayed autoresuscitation in humans even though the Maastricht protocol (developed by the University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland) acknowledged this phenomenon and required at least 10 minutes to elapse after cardiorespiratory arrest before starting organ procurement.[22] The 10 minute waiting time did not compromise the quality of the organs procured.

The cardiorespiratory death criteria for organ procurement also ignore cardiac electrical activity (such as pulseless electrical activity or ventricular fibrillation) on an electrocardiogram. Research with cardiac ultrasonography and indwelling arterial catheters confirms that pulseless cardiac electrical activity can be associated with cardiac mechanical contractions, although these contractions are too weak to be detected by blood pressure monitoring.[23] The presence of cardiac electrical activity on an electrocardiogram can also increase the likelihood that delayed autoresuscitation will occur.[19,20] Furthermore, whether there is brain electrical activity or neurologic function when cardiac electrical activity is still observed on an electrocardiogram remains unknown.[24] It can be argued that donors who have already suffered severe neurologic injury cannot have meaningful neurologic function at the time of cardiorespiratory death. However, the presence of brain activity becomes relevant for organ donors with intact neurologic and brain function prior to cardiorespiratory arrest when only cardiorespiratory criteria for organ procurement are being used.[4,8,9]

In situ circulatory support with extracorporeal perfusion in organ donors has also refuted that cardiorespiratory arrest for 5 minutes fulfills the UDDA requirement because reversibility can occur during the procurement process. In situ extracorporeal perfusion is initiated 5 minutes after cardiorespiratory arrest of donors in order to preserve organs for procurement.[25] Coronary and cerebral reperfusion can lead to the return of cardiac and neurologic functions (also called reanimation) of donors during the procurement process. Mechanical occlusion of the aortic arch and pharmacological agents are required to suppress donor reanimation during organ procurement.[26] Martin et al. documented that in situ extracorporeal perfusion returned full neurologic and cardiac function 25 minute after cardiorespiratory arrest that occurred outside the hospital.[27] Similar observations of full neurologic recovery and survival to hospital discharge were reported after in situ extracorporeal perfusion for in-hospital cardiorespiratory arrest.[28] These observations confirm that the time required for irreversible loss of neurologic function after cessation of circulation is much longer than the 2-5 minutes of cardiorespiratory arrest required to begin the process of organ procurement in NHBOD.

The incidence of donor reanimation during procurement is unknown because its reporting violates the dead donor rule and can create legal concerns.[11] It can be argued that reanimation of organ donors is irrelevant because it does not mean survival. However, the occurrence of reanimation invalidates the premise that the cardiorespiratory criteria for organ procurement comply with the uniform determination of death. Others have accepted the inaccuracy of these criteria for determining death for procurement of organs from deceased donors and proposed abandoning the dead donor rule in order to permit recovery of transplantable organs before death.[29]

In the face of the uncertainty in determining death and in response to a media and marketing campaign by organ procurement organizations (OPOs) to promote public enrollment in deceased organ donation, the transplant community renamed NHBOD "cardiac death" organ donation.[30,31] The use of the term cardiac death is scientifically inaccurate and perhaps misleading. This term is used to denote the cessation of circulation and cardiac pump activity. The term cardiac death can be misinterpreted as meaning the heart has irreversibly ceased at the time of procurement, thus contradicting the scientific evidence for spontaneous resumption of cardiac function and autoresuscitation.[19,20] Alternatively, the use of this term can falsely imply that neurologic activity or brain stem function has ceased irreversibly after loss of cardiac activity, when scientific evidence suggests that brain stem function can remain after cardiac arrest.[32]"

Consent for Organ Donation
"Several state laws and federal regulations have been enacted to ensure that organ donation and transplantation practice comply with the ethical and legal standards of society (Table 1). The current regulations require hospitals across the United States to provde regional OPOs with early notification of all patients whose deaths are imminent before life support has been withdrawn so that discussion of organ donation with surrogate decision makers can be initiated independently and consent obtained.[3,5,9] The Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative has set a goal of each OPO accomplishing a target organ donation rate of 75% or higher at local hospitals within an assigned donation service area (DSA).[1,2,5] The financial and administrative incentives for the OPO to achieve that target organ donation rate have introduced undisclosed conflict within the donation consent process.[33] Self-serving bias of OPOs can influence whether pertinent information necessary for surrogate decision makers to provide informed consent is disclosed.[34] As an example of this bias, alternative options for care and palliation may be discussed with surrogate decision makers with less enthusiasm than are the benefits and 'altruistic' notion of organ donation. In obtaining donation consent, OPOs often avoid disclosing details of perimortem interventions performed on donors that are required for successful procurement of transplantable organs.[10,34,35] After receiving consent for organ donation, OPO staffs also assume the responsibility of planning donor medical care and treatment pathways essential for maintaining organ viability and of preparing for subsequent procurement.[5,36] In essence, the care of the dying patient is guided by a team whose primary interest is the preservation of organs until procurement has been accomplished.

The Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (UAGA) assigns explicit priority to the donor's expressed intent so that consent for organ donation becomes irrevocable and does not require the consent or concurrence of any person after the donor's death (Table 1).[9,37] The donor's authorization to donate, recorded on an organ donor card, the individual's driver's license, or a donor registry, becomes a legally binding advance directive. The UAGA amendment enables OPOs to procure organs without family consent and in certain instances after family refusal to donate.[37]

Other consent options for organ donation from deceased donors have been proposed to maximize OPO recovery of transplantable organs in the United States (Table 2).[8] The IOM has considered presumed consent for organ donation as a favorable option.[8] Presumed consent means the default option is consent to donation, that if an individual has not expressly rejected donation, that individual is considered to have consented to organ donation. Legislative enactment of presumed consent enables OPOs to avoid the potential for surrogates to deny consent for donation, thus increasing the pool of future organ donors. The revised UAGA replaces 'nondonation' with the 'intent to donate organs' as the default option. In the default option, all measures necessary to ensure the medical suitability of an organ for transplantation can not be withheld or withdrawn until the OPO has determined medical suitability of the individual as a prospective donor (Table 1). The default option overrides the expression of intent in a declaration or advance health-care directives not to have life prolonged by withholding or withdrawing life support system unless the individual has expressed refusal of donation (Table 1 and Table 2). The revised UAGA presumes that for prospective donors the desire to save lives by making an anatomical gift trumps the desire to have life support systems withheld or withdrawn. Mandated consent (or conscription) has also been proposed for recovery of cadaveric organs (Table 2).[38] Under mandated consent, consent for organ donation is automatic from all deceased individuals; therefore, OPOs would not require or request consent because removal of all needed transplantable cadaveric organs would be compulsory. OPO staffs would no longer have to discuss organ procurement from potential donors with family members or other surrogates. An alternative form of donation consent is mandated choice, which requires each individual to decide in advance either to agree to organ donation or to refuse it. Mandated choice is the IOM's least favorite option because it would require extensive public informational programs on organ donation to facilitate individual choices and decision making (Table 2).[8]"

End-of-Life Care
"Quality of end-of-life (EOL) care for an organ donor, as for any individual whose treatment is being withdrawn, is considered the highest priority of care and must not be compromised by the donation process. Yet no studies have investigated the impact of organ donation on the quality of EOL care in NHBOD.[35] Previous reports have criticized the quality of EOL care offered to dying patients in intensive care units (ICUs).[39,40] Many of these patients are undergoing withdrawal of life support in anticipation of death and are considered candidates for NHBOD. The Robert Wood Johnson Foundation (RWJF) Critical Care End-Of-Life Peer Workgroup developed 53 EOL quality indicators to standardize and measure the quality of EOL care.[41] These quality indicators, organized in 7 domains, focus on delivering patient-and family-centered care and facilitating a 'good death' experience in the ICU (Table 3).

In a subsequent U.S. survey, the Critical Care Peer Workgroup of the Promoting Excellence in End-of-Life Care Project reported that more than 75% of ICUs were still not monitoring the quality of EOL care.[42] The survey also identified multiple barriers to optimal EOL care found in most ICUs. The study group proposed several strategies to overcome these barriers and improve the quality of EOL care (Table 3).[42,43] It can also be inferred from the survey findings that most ICUs are unprepared and lack the necessary tools to appropriately inform patients and families of the trade-off in EOL care for NHBOD. The President's Council for Bioethics has also warned that NHBOD can transform EOL care from a 'peaceful dignified death' into a profanely 'high-tech death' experience for donors' families.[10]

Several aspects of medical care that are neither palliative nor beneficial are performed for donor management for NHBOD and can explain the feared transformation of the death experience. The revised UAGA reaffirms that all measures necessary to ensure the medical suitability of an organ for transplantation cannot be withheld or withdrawn from the prospective donor and overrides the expression of intent by a prospective donor in either a declaration or advance health-care directive not to have life prolonged by use of life support systems (Table 1).[9] The 2007 amendment to revised UAGA section 21 recognizes the conflict between all measures necessary to ensure organs viability for transplantation and appropriate EOL care and requires the attending physician and OPO to resolve the conflict with the prospective donor or surrogate decision-maker.[9]

OPOs apply donor management critical pathways to potential organ donors in order to maintain organ viability for successful execution of organ procurement.[36] The University of Wisconsin developed a protocol and an evaluation tool to determine the eligibility of potential candidates for NHBOD.[44] The protocol entails temporary discontinuation of mechanical ventilation for a trial of spontaneous respiration lasting up to 10 minutes to determine the likelihood of cardiorespiratory death within 60-90 minutes of the withdrawal of life support. Those patients predicted by the University of Wisconsin evaluation tool to survive a longer time are not candidates for NHBOD and are transferred to palliative care. Those patients who meet the necessary criteria of the University of Wisconsin evaluation tool become candidates for NHBOD and undergo additional antemortem testing, invasive vascular instrumentation, and infusion of medications essential for organ preservation.[36] The instrumentation and medications used for organ preservation can also expedite death on withdrawal of life support.[45] Other interventions (such as circulatory support with invasive and noninvasive devices, extracorporeal perfusion and oxygenation, endotracheal reintubation, mechanical ventilation, and bronchoscopy) are performed when cardiorespiratory death is pronounced in order to maintain organ viability and can inadvertently reanimate the donor during the procurement process.[26]

The process of obtaining donation consent and subsequent donor management protocols for NHBOD deviate from more than 60% of the RWJF quality indicators recommended for optimal EOL care.[35,36,41] Therefore, NHBOD can have a profound impact on the quality of EOL care. There has been a recent proposal to abbreviate the original RWJF quality indicators to include 14 of the 53 (26%) original quality indicators described for optimal EOL care in the ICU (Table 3).[46] Many of the quality indicators expected to be negatively affected by NHBOD are not included in the proposal for an abbreviated list. There has been a concern that the application of an abbreviated rather than a comprehensive metrics for EOL care can portray an incomplete assessment and perhaps misinform donors and their families about the potential trade-off in EOL care. The President's Council on Bioethics has emphasized that comprehensive evaluation of the quality of EOL care is an ethical imperative so that families can decide if the trade-off is acceptable for organ donation.[10] Deciding to donate organs at the end of life can be stressful for many families, and therefore they must be fully informed of the possible consequences. Posttraumatic stress disorders, anxiety, depression, and decreased quality of life have been reported in the deceased's family members who shared in stressful EOL decisions.[47] Posttraumatic stress disorders have been reported in family members of deceased organ donors.[48] Organ-focused behavior by professionals requesting consent for organ donation and ambivalent decision making by family members appeared to increase the risk of relatives of deceased donors subsequently developing traumatic memories and stress disorders. The processes required for successful accomplishment of donation consent and subsequent organ recovery can interfere with many of the interventions that lessen the burden of bereavement of relatives of ICU decedents.[49]

The variability in decision making by health care providers about medical futility and EOL care has been given as a reason for concern about the implementation of NHBOD.[50] The variability of EOL practice raises the possibility of conflicted decision making on medical futility within institutions that have transplant programs.[50] Ethical conflicts and moral distress have been reported among health care providers who were directly involved in organ procurement in NHBOD.[51] The pressure to recover transplantable organs from NHBOD candidates has been associated with health care professionals' perception of euthanasia and premature determination of medical futility and withdrawal of life support. The long-term psychological impact of NHBOD practice on caregivers, health care providers, and professionals remains unknown."

Conclusions
"In conclusion, NHBOD influences medical care at critical time points to maximize the procurement of transplantable organs and minimize their warm ischemia time with negative consequences on the EOL care for the prospective donors and their families (see Figure 1).

Mandatory implementation of NHBOD in the face of difficulties surrounding the quality of EOL care for donors raises concern across the medical profession and community. There is a need for better scientific validation of the timing of organ procurement to ensure that organ recovery is not the irreversible event defining death in NHBOD. The desire of OPOs or their affiliates to maximize recovery of transplantable organs introduces self-serving bias into obtaining consent for organ donation and violates the basic tenet of true informed consent. The use of comprehensive quality indicators of EOL care will help to determine the impact of NHBOD on donors, families, caregivers, and health care providers."

References
1. Marks WH, Wagner D, Pearson TC, et al. Organ donation and utilization, 1995-2004: Entering the collaborative era. Am J Transplant. 2006;6:1101-1110.
2. U.S. Department of Health and Human Servcies—Organ Donation and Transplant Breakthrough Collaborative. Measurement strategy: Organ Donation and Transplant Breakthrough Collaborative. Available at: http://www. organdonationnow.org/. Accessed December 15, 2006.
3. U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Advisory Committee on Organ Transplantation. Consensus Recommendations to the HHS Secretary. Available at: http:// www.organdonor.gov/research/acot.htm. Accessed January 30, 2007.
Bernat JL, D'Alessandro AM, Port FK, et al. Report of a National Conference on Donation after Cardiac Death. Am J Transplant. 2006;6:281-291.
4. Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services, Department of Health and Human Services.
5. Medicare and Medicaid Programs. Conditions for coverage for organ procurement organizations (OPOs); final rule. Federal Register. 2006;71: 30981-31054.
6. [JCAHO] Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations. Health care at the crossroads: strategies for narrowing the organ donation gap and protecting patients. Availableat:http://www.jointcommission.org/PublicPolicy/ organ_donation.htm. Accessed January 30, 2007.
7. [JCAHO] Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations. Revisions to Standard LD.3.110. Jt Comm Perspect. 2006;26:7.
8. Committee on Increasing Rates of Organ Donation-Board on Health Sciences Policy-Institute of Medicine. Organ Donation: Opportunities for Action. Washington, DC: National Academies Press; 2006.
9. National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. Revised Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (2006) and Amendment to Section 21 (2007). http://www.law.upenn.edu/bll/ulc/uaga/2006final.htm and http://www.anatomicalgiftact.org/DesktopDefault.aspx?tabindex=0&tabid=1. Accessed April8,2007.
10. Rubenstein A, Cohen E, Jackson E. The definition of death and the ethics of organ procurement from the deceased. The President's Council on Bioethics. Available at: http://www. bioethics.gov/background/rubenstein.htmlandhttp://www. bioethics.gov/transcripts/sept06/session1.html. Accessed January 30, 2007.
11. Menikoff J. The importance of being dead: non-heart-beating organ donation. Issues Law Med. 2002;18:3-20.
12. National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. The Uniform Determination of Death Act. Available at: http://www.law.upenn.edu/bll/ulc/fnact99/1980s/udda80. htm. Accessed January 30, 2007.
13. DeVita MA, Snyder JV. Development of the University of Pittsburgh Medical Center policy for the care of terminally ill patients who may become organ donors after death following the removal of life support. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1993;3:131-143.
14. Committee on Non-Heart-Beating Transplantation II—The Scientific and Ethical Basis for Practice and Protocols Division of Health Care Services, Institute of Medicine. Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation: Practice and Protocols. Washington, DC: National Academy Press; 2000.
15. Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine; Society of Critical Care Medicine. Recommendations for nonheartbeating organ donation: a position paper by the Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine, Society of Critical Care Medicine. Crit Care Med. 2001; 29:1826-1831.
16. DeVita MA, Snyder JV, Arnold RM, Siminoff LA. Observations of withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment from patients who became non-heart-beating organ donors. Crit Care Med. 2000;28:1709-1712.
17. DeVita MA. The death watch: certifying death using cardiac criteria. Prog Transplant. 2001;11:58-66.
18. Zawistowski CA, DeVita MA. A descriptive study of children dying in the pediatric intensive care unit after withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment. Ped Crit Care Med. 2004;5:216-223.
19. Maleck WH, Piper SN, Triem J, Boldt J, Zittel FU. Unexpected return of spontaneous circulation after cessation of resuscitation (Lazarus phenomenon). Resuscitation. 1998; 39:125-128.
20. Adhiyaman V, Sundaram R. The Lazarus phenomenon JR Coll Physicians Edinb. 2002;32:9-13.
21. Paradis NA, Martin GB, Rivers EP, et al. Coronary perfusion pressure and the return of spontaneous circulation in human cardiopulmonary resuscitation. JAMA. 1990;263:11061113.
22. Weber M, Dindo D, Demartines N, Ambuhl PM, Clavien P-A. Kidney transplantation from donors without a heartbeat. N Engl J Med. 2002;347:248-255.
23. American Heart Association. Management of cardiac arrest. Circulation. 2005;112:IV-58-IV-66.
24. Whetstine L, Streat S, Darwin M, Crippen D. Pro/con ethics debate: When is dead really dead? Crit Care. 2005;9:538-542
25. Magliocca JF, Magee JC, Rowe SA, et al. Extracorporeal support for organ donation after cardiac death effectively expands the donor pool. J Trauma-Injury Infect Crit Care. 2005;58:1095-1101; discussion 1101-1092.
26. Dejohn C, Zwischenberger JB. Ethical implications of extracorporeal interval support for organ retrieval (EISOR). ASAIO J. 2006;52:119-122.
27. Martin GB, Rivers EP, Paradis NA, Goetting MG, Morris DC, Nowak RM. Emergency department cardiopulmonary bypass in the treatment of human cardiac arrest. Chest. 1998; 113:743-751.
28. Younger JG, Schreiner RJ, Swaniker F, Hirschl RB, Chapman RA, Bartlett RH. Extracorporeal resuscitation of cardiac arrest. Acad Emerg Med. 1999;6:700-707.
29. Truog RD, Robinson WM. Role of brain death and the dead-donor rule in the ethics of organ transplantation. Crit Care Med. 2003;31:2391-2396.
30. Merion RM, Vinokur AD, Couper MP, et al. Internet-based intervention to promote organ donor registry participation and family notification. Transplantation. 2003;75:1175-1179.
31. The Transplant Resource Center of Maryland. Media Memo. Available at: http://www.mdtransplant.org/beta/images/ users/1/Terminology.pdf. Accessed January 30, 2007.
32. Manole MD, Hickey RW. Preterminal gasping and effects on the cardiac function. Crit Care Med. 2006;34(suppl):S438– S441.
33. Ranjan D, Schmonsky K, Johnston T, Jeon H, Bouneva I, Erway E. Financial analysis of potential donor management at a Medicare-approved transplant hospital. Am J Transplant. 2006;6:199-204.
34. Woien S, Rady MY, Verheijde JL, McGregor J. Organ Procurement Organizations Internet Enrollment for Organ Donation: Abandoning Informed Consent. BMC Med Ethics 2006;7:14-23 Available at: http://www.biomedcentral.com/ 1472-6939/7/14.
35. Rady MY, Verheijde JL, McGregor J. Organ donation after circulatory death: the forgotten donor. Crit Care. 2006; 10: 166-169. Available at: http://ccforum.com/content/10/5/166.
36. United Network for Organ Sharing—Donor Management Critical Pathway. Donor management critical pathway. Available at: http://www.unos.org/resources/donorManagement.asp?index=2. Accessed January30,2007.
37. The HHS Secretary's Advisory Committee on Organ Transplantation. State Law and OPO Practice. State laws on adoption of the 1987 Amendments for Anatomical Gifting. Available at: http://www.organdonor.gov/research/acotapp6. htm. Accessed January 25 2007.
38. Spital A. Conscription of cadaveric organs: we need to start talking about it. Am J Transplant. 2005;5:1170-1171.
39. Last Acts Committee. Means to a better end. a report on dying in America today. Available at: http://www.rwjf.org/ files/publications/other/meansbetterend.pdf and http:// www.endoflifecommission.org/end_pages/national_report. htm#. Accessed January 30, 2006.
40. Wennberg JE, Fisher ES, Stukel TA, Skinner JS, Sharp SM, Bronner KK. Use of hospitals, physician visits, and hospice care during last six months of life among cohorts loyal to highly respected hospitals in the United States. Brit Med J. 2004;28:607-610.
41. Clarke E, Curtis J, Luce J, et al. Quality indicators for end-of-life care in the intensive care unit. Crit Care Med. 2003; 31:2255-2262.
42. Nelson JE, Angus DC, Weissfeld LA, et al. End-of-life care for the critically ill: a national intensive care unit survey. Crit Care Med. 2006;34:2547-2553.
43. Beckstrand RL, Callister LC, Kirchhoff KT. Providing a "good death": critical care nurses' suggestions for improving end-of-life care. Am J Crit Care. 2006;15:38-45.
44. Lewis J, Peltier J, Nelson H, et al. Development of the University of Wisconsin donation after cardiac death evaluation tool. Prog Transplant. 2003;13:265-273.
45. Motta ED. The ethics of heparin administration to the potential non-heart-beating organ donor. J Prof Nurs. 2005;21:97-102.
46. Mularski RA, Curtis JR, Billings JA, et al. Proposed quality measures for palliative care in the critically ill: a consensus from the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation Critical Care Workgroup. Crit Care Med. 2006;34:S404–S411.
47. Azoulay E, Pochard F, Kentish-Barnes N, et al. Risk of posttraumatic stress symptoms in family members of intensive care unit patients. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2005;171:987-994.
48. Kesselring A, Kainz M, Kiss A. Traumatic memories of relatives regarding brain death, request for organ donation and interactions with professionals in the ICU. Am J Transplant. 2007;7:211-217.
49. Lautrette A, Darmon M, Megarbane B, et al. A communication strategy and brochure for relatives of patients dying in the ICU. N Engl J Med. 2007;356:469-478.
50. Doig CJ. Is the Canadian health care system ready for donation after cardiac death? A note of caution. Can Med Assoc J. 2006;175:905.
51. Mandell MS, Zamudio S, Seem D, et al. National evaluation of healthcare provider attitudes toward organ donation after cardiac death. Crit Care Med. 2006;34:2952-2958.
52.NationalConferenceofCommissionersonUniformStateLaws.UniformLawCommissioners.Availableat:http://www.nccusl.org/Update/DesktopDefault.aspx?tabindex=2&tabid=60.AccessedJan-uary30,2007.
53. Office of the Law Revision Counsel of the U.S. House of Representatives. United States Code, 2000 Edition, Supplement 2. Available at: http://www.gpoaccess.gov/uscode/ index.html. Accessed January 30, 2007.
54. Code of Federal Regulations. Code of Federal Regulations (CFR). Available at: http://www.gpoaccess.gov/cfr/ index.html. Accessed January 30, 2007.

Source:
"'Non-Heart-Beating,' or 'Cardiac Death,' Organ Donation : Why We Should Care"
M. Y. Rady, MD, PhD, FCCM, Professor of Medicine, Mayo Clinic College of Medicine, Department of Critical Care Medicine, Mayo Clinic Hospital, 5777 East Mayo Boulevard, Phoenix, AZ 85054; Fax: (480) 342-1388; E-mail: rady.mohamed@mayo.edu. In : Journal of Hospital Medicine. 2007;2(5):324-334. Copyright 2007 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.